Friday, November 30, 2007

Readability of Quintilian versus Aristotle

Stephanie and I discussed how much easier it was to read the Quintilian section. We both brought up the fact that the translation issue and language difference (Latin to English versus Ancient Greek to English) could have made the difference. Is Latin closer to English and therefore make it easier to translate? Does anyone have any ideas about that? I also wondered if the fact that On Rhetoric is widely accepted to be Aristotle's lecture notes had much to do with the texts lack of readability. Contrasted with Aristotle's work, Quintilian's piece seems to be written for others to read and grasp the examples, if not for publication. I wonder t oo, if the reason Quintilian's reading was easier because we have read many other writers and are becoming proficient in reading such works. And he appears to write like Plato a little bit- by asking many questions and trying to answer them. This style seems a bit easier to grasp then long sentences with many asides.

I think it is interesting that both men struggle with the issue of 'good' and 'bad' rhetoric as well as 'good' and 'bad' orators or rhetors. In Book 12, Quintilian seems to be struggling with it. He does not answer the question directly but obviously finds the answers unsatisfactory because he keeps returning to the point.

My final point- which has been bugging me for sometime is 'is there a test or a way of knowing if someone is being sincere or simply faking it?' I ask because Quintilian makes the assumption that only a 'good man' can be a true orator, yet how can we really tell? Albert Einstein (recalling physics) said there is no experiment that can differentiate between the force of gravity and a body moving at 9.8 meters/(second)^2. Similarly, if someone 'acts' or behaves 'good' how can we differentiate that from someone who is genuinely 'good'? OK, that is my 2 cents worth!

Wednesday, November 28, 2007

Wanted: Greek word for character

I have been working on my paper for this class, and I find myself in need of a Greek term to help explain my point. I am looking at the role characters played in Greek rhetoric. By this I mean the creation of "fictional" characters, not moral character (ethos). I am currently trying to make the distinction between these two types of character, but not getting very far in the clarity department, since both words are still character. I was thinking if I could find the greek equivalent to fictional character, (or something close) I could use that and ethos instead. I am currently looking for this word myself, but thought there might be a chance that someone else has run across something that is close in the wiki assignment. Anyone have any ideas?

Alyssa

Wednesday, November 21, 2007

Lantham's teasingly serious question

I want to make it clear that I had to sleep for two days straight to be able to really comprehend Lantham, even though I found his style to be clear as glacier water and equally refreshing. If I hadn't, I'd be weeping softly into my keyboard right about now; I'm supposed to be shopping and then cooking for ten or so.

Lantham teases, I think, because this is such a stunningly obvious question, once you see it, yet one that is so intrinsically bound up in our ego that it is difficult to see. (Face it, deciding that we have something important to say, important enough to run out and spend a lot of money for a piece of paper that gives us the right to out our foot down on discussions and be experts requires loads of ego; also continuing to go after we get beat about by the mass of knowledge that does not flatter us nor make us happy. We're either masochists or there is something in the process and/or end that we value.)

The Q question: What is good? What should be valued, encouraged? What intersection can the inner being (the ethics, the morals) have with the knowledge we gain through study?

God, these are almost dirty phrases. I have to stop myself from giggling nervously and looking away, and I blush but rarely anymore. And for good reason: the humanities have been put into a position that makes it nearly impossible to justify anything with a straight face. We insist, when looking for funding or justifying what looks like a twisty sort of self-gratification to our relatives who are either in the hard sciences or without the ivory tower (yeah, yeah-- TMI), that the education we have will improve the world, full in the face of a total lack of direct correlation at anything more than a few times, as opposed to the total redemption we claim for our education. (p 164-5)

The divisions of Lantham's discipline of discourse (p 159) into our departments is not, I think without its benefits to us, but not in the sterile stagnation that Ramus intends it (p 157-9). In terms of the benefits of division, those greatly artificial distinctions provide us with the ability to skip along a great variety of points of view, of positional lenses, so that we may, at any given point in time (in potential, according to skill and training) chose to see a given subject a number of different ways.

Unfortunately, this results in a double-brained split when it comes to articulating the things we know to be true and the underpinning for our studies (p 160-61, 164); every single one of us has a goal to which we aspire, and the difficulty with splitting how we know, what we know and how we express it is that it has a tendency to obscure the most basic assumptions we make about the objects of our study. When we study, we assume a trend, a course of action, a necessity and, even unconsciously, a result. (p 162) We shape our study by these underlying assumptions, and the rigorous fragmentation of the humanities (though it is never rigorously observed) only encourages us not to think about what we're doing very closely. We are taught, to a great degree, to focus on larger concerns (like social justice, for those of us who plan to be teachers), obscuring why we're there and what, exactly, we think we're up to.

Of course, to ask that question is also to ask where we think good, bad and true come into the equation, hence the strong and weak defenses, respectively either the orator must be the site for morality or the practice must be. I think it's pretty clear that rhetoric assumes the lowest common denominator in audiences; as such it gives the appearance, when the morality of rhetoric is situated in the words themselves, of being negative and therefore inherently bad (p 160-61).

I'm not sure we should be uncomfortable with the practice our best values and hope for our students (p 164). If we do not treat the people we seek to teach as if they should be able to make their own decisions, it is deeply hypocritical. Genuine enlightenment you can take or leave. Coercion you must work much harder to get out from under. (p 165)

On page 166, Lantham makes a case for the weak defense being not only that which situates the morality of rhetoric in the outside world and the strong being the situation of morality in the ethos of the orator, making the person of the rhetor the place in which rhetoric must marry metaphysics and determine what of the orator enters the words (in other words, the truth value of a given rhetorical statement is maintained and defined by the orator as a discrete event in time.) The responsibility for rhetorical awareness and for the probable consequence also lies in the rhetor, in their ability and intentions.

That's some slick stuff, there.

Technology has a huge effect on the divisions between departments and fields of study; when we are forced to communicate effectively across culture as well as departmental tribe, it forces us to codify yet again and to examine our own subjectivity (p 167). Our communication, where it is formalized and codified (like in papers, say) force us to articulate false absolutes, in full knowledge that we know better, for the express purpose of simplification and focus. As we try to force that kind of communication on something a little more lively than a sheet of paper, we attempt to re-create that narrowing and cannot; technology forces us to try and restructure the system which we use to codify and also forces a confrontation with the Q question, because we have great difficulty maintaining those artificial distinctions between ethos and practice in the face of an audience outside our commonplace (p 167-8). The distinction, as Lantham points out all over, relies on an intellectual slight-of-hand, although I would add that the audience, whether they know it or not, have to agree to look the other way for the trick, something that we cannot rely on a new audience to do.

The response to shifting fields of meaning should not be to throw one's hands up in the air and resign the probing of the individual to the language which makes them so, nor should it be the refusal to address the ethos behind it (p 169). (And thank god for that, because some of the semantic fancy dancing I end up doing makes my head ache.)

But this does not posit the rhetor as free of being affected by his or her own rhetoric (and that kind of absolutist thinking should get one a spank; funny how post-modernism teaches us not to and yet we apply it every which way) (p 169). The actor is also acted on, the relationship is complicated and cannot be simplified to a 'you first' equation.

And, in what has to be rehashed, Lantham reminds the reader that to insist on the primacy of the facts is to ignore the fact that the facts are so influenced by the person assembling them that they offer up their own interpretation. (p 170-71) Rhetoric insists that any given set of facts is a pastiche of everything the presenter has to offer, and as such rhetoric must be 'big', or at least bigger than the individual presenting. The world will be saved by the current events club, indeed. The facts are neither dry nor virtuous, but they are sometimes useful.

See what lengths I'll go to not to bake a turkey?

And if I've heard my kids complain once, I've heard them complain a million times: why are we learning all this shite we aren't going to use? (p 171) My answer for them has been that real learning is a thing you do for the love of it, in your spare time. I spend a lot of time trying to illustrate to them, and to a particularly skeptical group of ten year olds down in the valley, that there actually are connections between the subjects, mostly in application. A short seminar on creative writing can quickly segueway into physics and how to present the death of a patient to their family. Sometimes I feel stupid because I feel as if I meander all over the damn place (no coherence here, no sir), but in retrospect, I think I won't sweat the cross-subject jaunts; if nothing else, I'm demonstrating that curiosity can be useful and somewhat satisfying.

As someone who's about to compose a MFA jeremiad (p 173), I was stung and amused. I should hope mine is not plaintive nor conciliatory in tone. I owe no defense of my study to anyone but my kids and bf, and to my mind the place of the humanities is, frankly, kinda obvious. (Which probably means I'm missing something.) How unsatisfying and amusing I find it, with my collective years of training in compartmentalizing and rigid classification, to hear that the defense of the humanities is in the person, not the institution. That view must make hiring a painful process of interviews and a giant pain in the hiney. We get certified to greatly simplify that process, don't we?

When in doubt, add a department (p 173). Well, it certainly guarantees more jobs. And if we all disagree, we can retreat behind our disciplinary walls, safe in the knowledge that we're so specialized (and much smarter) that the only people we need to have understand us are those that both agree with us and share our discipline. Hence the sterility, if you buy contact zone theory. And I do, but it might be because I like a good fight.

And now, having divided himself, Lantham has to conquer. He's already proved he sees (p 174). And by conquer, I mean provide a plan for replicating his theoretical viewpoint (I always have trouble trusting theories that cannot provide a plan for being implemented; they make me nervous, because they're usually trying to hide the terms by which the theory could be implemented.)

So if the books cannot teach themselves, they cannot be neutral, either. Same for rhetoric, Lantham has (reluctantly) persuaded me (p 174). Okay then, I suppose there can be bad arguments (although I usually save that distinction for arguments that are radically incomplete. Let's see how he splits this hair.

The feminist question to the 'Great Books' approach is very apropos to Lantham's argument. Their question has always been how these books are determined to be great (and by implication, who has been arbitrarily left out of the running) (p 176). I am guessing that Lantham's statement that religion will ruin the asking of the Q question has as much to do with a cannonical refusal to be self-aware or to self-examine as his objection to the Great books proposition for teaching/moralizing.

There is very definitely a tension between the people who practice and the people who prefer to theorize (p 177). Sometimes this is expressed as the tower versus everyone else, sometimes as people claiming 'freedom' for theory without realizing that their unexamined values have artificially limited it already and people whose conceptions of theory must stem only from their experiences. Think I'm a touch slimy, if that definition is to be trusted, all my years in college aside.

Oh, there's a meritocracy all right, it is just neither universal nor clear. Me and the other right-thinking humans all agree on it. Unfortunately, they're all at the top of theirs, too. And, on second thought, looks like we're all looking at something different. Nevermind. (p 178)

The artificial distinctions that Lantham is at such pains to point out do tend to breed closed rhetorical spaces, in which the mind at work re-arranges all to fit preconceptions while unaware of the re-arrangement. Being the only rational creature in the universe will do that to you (p 178.)

The disingenuous nature of the divisions we practice makes it easier for us to lie but creates cognitive dissonance that can cause us acute discomfort, so we band together in a show of solidarity in our collective not asking (180-81).

So how do we address that division? (p 180-85) Do we claim that we can live separated from the effects of our actions and theories, at play in a sheltered university campus somewhere? Do we feel compelled to confront and act on the dissonance of that division?

The answer is 'that depends'. On us.

Purity of motives my right cheek! (p 187) Only, and if that, which I doubt, in the sense that we might most want some particular geegaw or certification. Our rhetorical play is never without effect and consequence, going every which way. I tend to agree with Lantham; it's only exciting when it's applied, when the whole mess of theory could go every which way. Like splat. (p 187)

The strong defense as (fairly) consistent contingency is an interesting argument (p 188.) I tend to agree that pretending our motivations are completely 'pure' is dangerous and liable to fail spectacularly (ahem, the Catholic priest scandals), but Lantham is careful not to rule out the possibility that some of our motivations can be 'noble' in scope. They just don't make up the bulk of our motivation.

Hmm, replicating a basis for morality based on practice to filter out problems. Nice one (p 188). Planning for problems has to go one better than denial or thoughtless attack.

To look at language with self-consciousness (as in false modesty) does, in fact, play games with language in a way that is not terribly productive. (p 189) And modeling requires great exposure and a great deal out of the teacher. Our education system cannot handle this kind of thing.

God, this essay would have done a great deal to simplify the Pedagogy of Creative Writing class I had last semester. Wish we had read it.

And pages 189-91 should be required reading at business schools. What loyalty would inspire an employee to contribute creatively to a company in an environment which punished creativity? Hell, for that matter what inspires an employee to contribute at all outside the company's rent of his/her body?

And now, I go back to touching a turkey.

Monday, November 19, 2007

Richard Lanham's Q Question

What is the Q Question?
What does Lanham mean by the "strong defense" and the "weak defense"?

I think if we can collectively answer these questions alone, we'll be able to move more readily to Lanham's arguments about curriculum and the rhetoric/philosophy split. And I do think re-articulating what Lanham has in mind in these early pages is difficult--so just give it a try.

Here' s a link to my framework for the Lanham reading with suggested additional pages for those of you who are interested in reading more.

Framing for Lanham Reading

Sunday, November 18, 2007

World of Wiki: Greek Terms

I've created an assignment to be accessed at

http://www.unm.edu/~sromano/english542/wiki.htm

Now, I know in class we talked about posting your Greek words to blogspot (here). And you can still do that. But now that I've experimented a bit with the wiki and given you some technical instructions, I'd really prefer that you post your work there. Think about it: the wiki will have a certain nebulous permanance (unless someone accidentally deletes it). Other student at UNM English will build upon and modify your postings. You can go back and bask in the pleasure of your own words! You can engage in an editing war with an unknown collaborator. You will learn how a wiki works and can then incorporate wiki-dom into your course syllabi or your own professional writing public presence. You owe it to teachers and professional writers in our program to lead the way.

Which of Aristotles emotions am I trying to invoke here?
The wiki:

http://greekrhetoricalterms.pbwiki.com/List-of-the-Terms-in-the-Greek-Rhetorical-Terms-Wiki

So let's go for the wiki. Problems? Let me know. Sarah brings her computer--we can gather round and see how it works.

Monday, November 5, 2007

Did Susan Jarrett Peg Aristotle Right as a Logos Snob?

Did Susan Jarrett Peg Aristotle Right as a Logos Snobor Was He Just Ahead of His Time for SeparatingLiterature and Poetry from Rhetoric?

I definitely see both aspects as I read through Book3. Arisotle continually divides and subdividesrhetoric and in the third book seems to focus onStyle, Arrangment, and Delivery. Part of thesedivisions serve to provide a common way of thinking,common vocabulary and such for the newly created area of rhetoric but also cause those on the fringes (non-logos users) to be excluded from the creation. At the same time he is moving language (especially oratory communications) into 2 distinct classes: creative literature and purposeful rhetoric.

He looks at form and almost immediately makes a comparison between oratory and play/ ordinary speech. He insists oratory should be different from tragedy and rhapsody and poetry as well as everyday speech. He also comments on the apects of voice in oratory. The elements of tone, rhythm, pitch, and volume canbe varied in giving a greater effect on the audience but at the same time he compares this negatively toacting. He negatively says that “those [performerswho give careful attention to these] are generally theones who win poetic contests; and just as actors aremore important than poets now in the poetic contests.” Once again he reiterates his dislike of the use ofpoetics in rhetoric. Though he compares delivery to acting, he goes on to say that these are artisticelements and have a great effect on audience. I also think it is insightful yet limiting that each personof a category, age, gender, etc., can only speak fromthat specific set of virtues of that group. I see thepoint that it is part of our ethos, but he seems tosay that we cannot argue something that is not in ourcharacter or morals. Like Tim points out, he doesseem to be contradicting himself, but I agree with Tim that using them rhetorically and conspicuously (asopposed to excessively and badly) that they can improve oratory. But he is definitely making a separation from the ‘lower’ uses of speech in playsand everyday speech from the ‘higher’ rhetoric. But aren’t these differences used in professional writing-we want to sound educated and actually interesting to our audience but we have to be careful of getting too creative and having our audience forget the purpose.

When discussing style and tropes, he remains consistent in moving away from poetic speaking and towards ‘professional’ speaking. His major rationale in preference for the metaphor, is that simile is used in poetry. In Dr. Shea’s class we talked about why high school teachers make such a big deal between the difference between the explicit simile and the implicit metaphor, and this may be the reason why. Aristotle himself makes such a difference when the actual difference is not so striking. Another area he spends time enumerating the differences between effective oratory style and poetics is diction. He defines lexis, word choice or diction, and goes on to enumerate, in his typical style, the uses and misuses of lexis. He often compares it to poetry, that we should mimic the rhythm but not the meter of poetry. So both in style and delivery he moves from poetry and the beauty of words into using the beauty of the words as a tool to convey a meaning-- an important distinction between the purposes of the genre.

So though he is privledging certain members of his society, Aristotle is also beginning the separation of language into literature/poetry/creative writing and rhetoric/professional writing. As we see in ourEnglish programs today, that distinction remains.

Sunday, November 4, 2007

Digging through the gloss...

As I read through Book Three, I began to get confused by Aristotle’s seeming flip-flopping. The thing that really confused me is that he seemed to be saying in some places that we should not obscure the meaning of our speeches from our audience—we should use clear, simple words and grammatical structures to avoid confusing them. But then he turns around and says we should avoid being known to our audience. So which is it, Ari, Ole Boy? Should our audience know us or shouldn’t they? Should they be able to understand what we mean, or should we try to hide it from them? What purpose, exactly, would hiding the meaning of our speeches from our audience serve? To make us seem more elevated and lofty in our intellectual obscurity? To confuse and baffle our audience into submission?

Then I decided that maybe I was glossing over the text, as it were (in the modern sense—not the glossing of antiquity). Maybe I wasn’t reading between the lines enough. Certainly it would help if Aristotle were here to read it aloud to us himself, because then we would be sure to catch all the nuances and inflections of meaning that begin to blur on the written page (and now I’m flip-flopping from my former position that the written word is superior to the spoken word...sigh...). Finally, after pacing around my office, reading Aristotle to the empty desks, an idea emerged from the fog in my brain. I think what he is trying to get at is that we should use language and syntax that our audience will understand, but that we should hide our technique to make our speech seem as though it is completely genuine and not premeditated because this will improve our ethos—it will appear as though we are speaking from our hearts and minds, not carefully plotting the best way to manipulate our audience into following the course of action we prescribe. So, if we cleverly disguise the framework, we will use logos to build our ethos and appeal to the audience through pathos? These are just some thoughts to start the ball rolling. I’ll keep digging...

Friday, November 2, 2007

Enthymemes, enthymemes!

Thanks to the state of Oregon for putting Measure 50 on the ballot! And thanks to "The News Hour" on PBS for a segment on the measure! I now have ENTHYMEMES!
If passed by the voters in Oregon, Measure 50 will increase the state's tobacco tax to pay for health care for children. In an interview with a smoker who is the mother of a diabetic son who receives state health insurance for his health care, she said she didn' think cigarettes should be taxed because there are a lot of other "bad things ou there. It's not because we smoke that kids get sick. " She also said that smokers didn't cause her son to be diabetic.

A tobacco industry lobbyist was shown speaking. He said: "We're taxing a convenient minority who has a habit that's unpopular and that's easy to pick on. What does an Oregon smoker have to do with the problem of uninsurance with kids today? Can you make a logical argument that because somebody lights up and smokes, they're somehow responsible for 117,000 kids being uninsured?" In the interview with the reporter, the lobbyist said, "The logic of using a smoking tax to fund health care is people quit smoking, you have no health care, and so you're rooting for one behavior - for people to quit. But on the back of that, you're trying to fund a program with money you hope disappears, and it makes no sense."

The next argument came from an advocate for the measure. She said, "Tobacco causes more than $1 billion a year in health care costs in Oregon. We know that exposure to second-hand smoke causes tens of thousands of hospital admissions for children." She also said, "No matter how hard we might try, we can't get everyone to quit smoking, and they won't." She said the tax would be a stable revenue source.

So, we see people on both sides of the argument using enthymemes to move people to support their positions. For the mom who smokes and the industry lobbyist, the smokers aren't doing anything one way or the other regarding child health care costs. The act of lighting up a cigarette does not affect the cost of health care, they say. Besides, there are other bad behaviors "out there." The advocate, on the other hand, ties her argument to the fact that second-hand smoke contributes to children's health problems and therefore, the smokers should help bear the costs of insuring these children. If you're going to smoke, you should take responsibility for what your smoking causes, she is saying.